Papers
Topics
Authors
Recent
Gemini 2.5 Flash
Gemini 2.5 Flash
173 tokens/sec
GPT-4o
7 tokens/sec
Gemini 2.5 Pro Pro
46 tokens/sec
o3 Pro
4 tokens/sec
GPT-4.1 Pro
38 tokens/sec
DeepSeek R1 via Azure Pro
28 tokens/sec
2000 character limit reached

The prior can generally only be understood in the context of the likelihood (1708.07487v2)

Published 24 Aug 2017 in stat.ME

Abstract: A key sticking point of Bayesian analysis is the choice of prior distribution, and there is a vast literature on potential defaults including uniform priors, Jeffreys' priors, reference priors, maximum entropy priors, and weakly informative priors. These methods, however, often manifest a key conceptual tension in prior modeling: a model encoding true prior information should be chosen without reference to the model of the measurement process, but almost all common prior modeling techniques are implicitly motivated by a reference likelihood. In this paper we resolve this apparent paradox by placing the choice of prior into the context of the entire Bayesian analysis, from inference to prediction to model evaluation.

Citations (374)

Summary

  • The paper argues that Bayesian priors must be understood and chosen in the context of the likelihood function, resolving a paradox where priors are often practically chosen with reference to the likelihood.
  • It challenges the conventional dichotomy between subjective and objective priors, suggesting their significance is best understood through their interaction with the likelihood across different analysis scenarios.
  • The authors emphasize that choosing priors requires considering robustness and predictive performance, advocating for priors that align with likelihood properties and domain knowledge, particularly in complex models.

The Contextual Role of Priors in Bayesian Analysis

The paper, "The prior can generally only be understood in the context of the likelihood," by Gelman, Simpson, and Betancourt, addresses the longstanding debate in the Bayesian statistical community regarding the choice and role of prior distributions in Bayesian inference. It highlights a critical paradox: while theoretically, priors should precede the data model, they are often chosen with reference to a likelihood function in practice.

Bayesian Priors: Their Roles and Interpretational Challenges

In Bayesian analysis, prior distributions serve to encode information relevant to the problem at hand or to stabilize inferences in complex, high-dimensional analyses. The paper challenges the conventional dichotomy between "subjective" and "objective" priors, suggesting instead characterizing them based on included information. The authors argue that the significance of a prior’s information is best understood in the context of its interaction with the likelihood.

The authors resolve the paradox of prior placement by asserting that the choice of prior should involve consideration of robustness, acknowledging that models are approximations and the impact of prior assumptions is contingent on the likelihood. They further argue for considering the roles played by priors within various Bayesian analyses scenarios.

The choice of priors cannot be decoupled from the data’s likelihood. For instance, in a scenario with binomial likelihood, the sensitivity to the chosen prior varies based on observed outcomes (e.g., a critical choice when y = 75 in contrast to when y = 40). This indicates that achieving robust analyses demands moving beyond a standard Bayesian workflow where priors are selected independent of the data-generating experiment.

Existing Approaches and Their Dependencies on Likelihood

The paper explores existing methods for setting priors, showing that they inherently depend on the likelihood to varying extents. From a maximalist approach, where priors encapsulate all available pre-data information, to minimalist approaches using noninformative priors, each method parallels the likelihood in some manner. Other prior types, such as structural and regularizing priors, are also discussed for their dependency on likelihood properties to enhance inference stability.

Insight through Illustrative Examples

An example illustrating the impact of priors is the paper by Kanazawa (2007) on attractiveness and sex ratio, where uniform priors were used to derive implications that seemed inconsistent with known biological stability in sex ratios. This example emphasizes the necessity for priors to be contextually valid, thereby determinable only through their interaction with the likelihood.

The authors argue that the complexity of a model dictates the ongoing relevance of the prior information even as sample sizes grow. They caution against indiscriminate use of uniform priors, which can result in misleading inferences, especially within highly complex analytical models.

Asymptotic Considerations and Complex Models

The work critiques the reliance on asymptotic arguments for prior construction, highlighting their limitations in contemporary large and intricately-structured datasets. The authors suggest that, given today’s data challenges, asymptotic considerations should more judiciously inform when priors might fail, rather than direct their design.

As the complexity of models increases, the nuances of how priors interact with the likelihood become more prominent. The problem is exemplified by Gaussian processes with covariance non-identifiability, where the authors recommend using priors that align with meaningful coordinate transformations in the parameter space.

Generative and Predictive Perspectives

Priors, though fundamentally probability measures, become meaningful only in conjunction with a likelihood that defines a data-generating process. Ensuring that priors yield reasonable data-generating mechanisms is vital, particularly for complex hierarchical models where subtle misalignments can significantly disturb inference.

The emphasis on prediction underscores the need for priors that facilitate robust posterior predictive performance and resist overfitting. While directed primarily at improving inference accuracy, the criterion also necessitates a priori mass allocation favoring simpler submodels to minimize overfitting risks—a task inherently challenging in high-dimensional scenarios.

Conclusion

The paper by Gelman et al. underscores that the role of a prior cannot be understood in isolation; its appropriateness is deeply rooted in its interaction with the likelihood and the predictive nature of the data-generating process. This integration is essential for effective modeling and impactful statistical inference. The conversation it prompts encourages researchers to rethink default priors and embrace priors that align closely with domain knowledge and likelihood considerations. The work has vital implications for the development of bespoke priors in Bayesian methodologies, urging practitioners to harmonize the theoretical and practical facets of Bayesian analysis.

X Twitter Logo Streamline Icon: https://streamlinehq.com