Papers
Topics
Authors
Recent
Gemini 2.5 Flash
Gemini 2.5 Flash
169 tokens/sec
GPT-4o
7 tokens/sec
Gemini 2.5 Pro Pro
45 tokens/sec
o3 Pro
4 tokens/sec
GPT-4.1 Pro
38 tokens/sec
DeepSeek R1 via Azure Pro
28 tokens/sec
2000 character limit reached

An Update Semantics for Defeasible Obligations (1301.6743v1)

Published 23 Jan 2013 in cs.AI and cs.LO

Abstract: The deontic logic DUS is a Deontic Update Semantics for prescriptive obligations based on the update semantics of Veltman. In DUS the definition of logical validity of obligations is not based on static truth values but on dynamic action transitions. In this paper prescriptive defeasible obligations are formalized in update semantics and the diagnostic problem of defeasible deontic logic is discussed. Assume a defeasible obligation normally A ought to be (done)' together withthe factA is not (done).' Is this an exception of the normality claim, or is it a violation of the obligation? In this paper we formalize the heuristic principle that it is a violation, unless there is a more specific overriding obligation. The underlying motivation from legal reasoning is that criminals should have as little opportunities as possible to excuse themselves by claiming that their behavior was exceptional rather than criminal.

Citations (8)

Summary

  • The paper introduces Deontic Update Semantics (DUS), a formal framework using update semantics to model and reason about defeasible obligations dynamically.
  • It addresses the diagnostic problem of distinguishing exceptions from violations by proposing a heuristic principle and using dynamic levels of ideality and normality.
  • The formalization aims to minimize opportunities for excusing non-compliance, utilizing state transitions to handle specificity and irrelevance in deontic reasoning.

The paper "An Update Semantics for Defeasible Obligations" introduces a dynamic perspective to deontic logic, specifically addressing defeasible obligations within the framework of update semantics. The central theme revolves around the formalization of prescriptive defeasible obligations using update semantics, drawing from Veltman's work, and tackles the diagnostic problem inherent in defeasible deontic logic.

The authors use the cottage housing regulations scenario to illustrate the complexities of reasoning with defeasible obligations. The core problem lies in differentiating between exceptions and violations when a defeasible obligation 'normally α\alpha ought to be (done)' is juxtaposed with the fact '-α\alpha is (done).' The paper posits a heuristic principle: such a scenario represents a violation unless a more specific, overriding obligation exists. This principle is motivated by a legal reasoning perspective that seeks to minimize opportunities for individuals to excuse criminal behavior by claiming exceptional circumstances.

The approach is formalized within a Deontic Update Semantics (DUS), where the validity of obligations is based on dynamic action transitions rather than static truth values. The logic aims to capture the intuition that criminals should have as few opportunities as possible to excuse themselves by claiming that their behavior was exceptional rather than criminal. The paper emphasizes that in the absence of a cliff, a penalty should be imposed for having a fence, as the initial obligation is violated. The difference between the antecedent of the second and third obligation is represented in the deontic states of the update semantics by two different orderings: the second gives rise to levels of exceptionality (inspired by preference-based approaches to defeasible reasoning) and the third gives rise to levels of ideality (inspired by preference-based approaches to deontic reasoning).

Key aspects of the formalization include:

  • Deontic States: These are possible-worlds models represented as tuples σ=(W,W,I,N,V)\sigma = (W, W*, \leq_I, \leq_N, V), where:
    • WW is a set of possible worlds.
    • WWW* \subseteq W represents an explicit sub-state used for the context of deliberation.
    • I\leq_I is a reflexive binary relation on WW representing ideality.
    • N\leq_N is a transitive, reflexive, and totally connected binary relation on WW representing normality.
    • VV is a valuation function for propositions at the worlds.
  • Deontic Language: This is a propositional language, LAL_A, extended with a dyadic operator oblige(α\alpha | β\beta), interpreted as "normally α\alpha ought to be (done), if β\beta is (done)."
  • Updates: The update function σ[+ϕ]\sigma[+ \phi] defines how a deontic state σ\sigma changes upon receiving a sentence ϕ\phi. Updates can either zoom in on the deontic state (for facts) or create ideality and normality levels (for obligations).
  • Reduction: The reduction of σ\sigma by oblige(α\alpha), denoted by σ\sigma - oblige(α\alpha | β\beta), modifies the ideality relation I\leq_I by removing pairs of worlds (w1,w2)(w_1, w_2) where w1w_1 is a most normal -αβ\alpha \land \beta world and w2w_2 is a most normal αβ\alpha \land \beta world.
  • Exception: The introduction of an exceptionality level in σ\sigma by oblige(α\alpha | β\beta), denoted by σ\sigma -N_N oblige(α\alpha | β\beta), modifies both the ideality relation I\leq_I and the normality relation N\leq_N to account for conflicts arising from the obligation.
  • Preference (pref): The paper uses the transitive closure of the ideality relation, β\leq_\beta, to define a preference relation pref(α\alpha, β\beta) = α\alpha. It holds if and only if for all worlds w1W1w_1 \in W_1 there is a world w2W2w_2 \in W_2 such that w2βw1w_2 \leq_\beta w_1 and there is no w3W1w_3 \in W_1 such that w3βw2w_3 \leq_\beta w_2, where W1W_1 and W2W_2 are the sets of the most normal -αβ\alpha \land \beta and αβ\alpha \land \beta worlds of WW, respectively.
  • Acceptance: A formula ϕ\phi is accepted in a deontic state σ\sigma, written as σϕ\sigma \Vdash \phi, if updating σ\sigma with ϕ\phi results in the same state, i.e., σ[+ϕ]=σ\sigma[+ \phi] = \sigma.
  • Validity: An argument from premises ϕ1,,ϕn\phi_1, \dots, \phi_n to a conclusion ϕ\phi is valid, denoted as ϕ1,,ϕn1ϕ\phi_1, \dots, \phi_n \vdash_1 \phi, if updating the minimal state 0 with the premises in that order yields a deontic state in which the conclusion is accepted. Nonmonotonic validity, denoted as ϕ1,,ϕnϕ\phi_1, \dots, \phi_n \Vdash \phi, requires that for all permutations π\pi of 1n1 \dots n such that {ϕπ(1),,ϕπ(n)[+]}ϕi\{\phi_{\pi(1)}, \dots, \phi_{\pi(n)}[+]\} \Vdash \phi_i for 1in1 \leq i \leq n, we also have ϕπ(1),,ϕπ(n)1ϕ\phi_{\pi(1)}, \dots, \phi_{\pi(n)} \vdash_1 \phi.

The paper illustrates how the logic formalizes the specificity principle, ensuring that more specific and conflicting obligations override more general ones. This is achieved through the introduction of exceptionality levels that dynamically re-evaluate hierarchical obligations. The logic also addresses the irrelevance problem, ensuring that irrelevant factors do not affect the acceptance of obligations.

Further, the paper introduces test operators ideal(α\alpha | β\beta) and ideal*(α\alpha | β\beta), analogous to Veltman's might and presumably operators, to evaluate norms within a specific deontic state. These operators test whether, ideally, α\alpha is (done) given β\beta is (done), considering both the context of justification and the context of deliberation.

The authors discuss Chisholm's paradox to illustrate how the operators oblige and ideal are combined, and how strengthening of the antecedent and weakening of the consequent are combined.

In summary, the paper offers a formal framework for reasoning about defeasible obligations, highlighting the importance of dynamic interpretation and context-sensitivity in deontic reasoning.